William Paley & Gottfried Leibniz
on God's existence


Urfan Ul Hassan
October 2023


God’s existence 

The questions surrounding God’s existence are philosophically speaking important; the reflections can help in understanding many difficult questions, for example in metaphysics and moral philosophy. The subject of God has had tremendous influence on history and continues to be important for individuals and their view on the cosmos and human life. Are there however good reasons for believing in The Unmoved Mover?  

There are different types of philosophical arguments for God’s existence; the three major ones are cosmological, ontological and design arguments. The cosmological arguments attempt to focus on how God is the only final explanation for things that are observed in the world, such as God being the original cause for any other cause, and is himself outside of space, time and thus causality itself. The design arguments focus on the high likelihood of the very specific machinery in the universe being designed by a mind. The ontological argument argues that God’s existence is self-explanatory. Many philosophers and thinkers throughout history have used a combination of these and other arguments to prove the existence of God, ranging from Aristotle to Descartes. 

Paley’s Design Argument

William Paley, born 1743, was a philosopher and theologian from England. Paley deduced that he could prove the existence of God by observing the universe and the apparent design in it; the analogy would be that just as a watch is designed with specific mechanics that are all in harmony with each other, so must the universe also have a Designer. Imagining that one stumbled upon a watch, it would be reasonable to assume that it must have been designed; one would not assume that it assembled itself, or that it happened by chance (Paley, 1802/2004, p. 34). The likelihood of this being a coincidence is so small that it is more reasonable to assume that it was designed; this means that if the watch, or the universe has a design, there must be a designer. Even if it was impossible to comprehend all the mechanics in the watch, or some parts remained undiscovered, or if it was broken, it would not weaken the argument that the watch is more than likely designed by a mind (Paley, 1802/2004, p. 36).  

Furthermore, the human mind’s inclination to find a pattern is not a convincing argument to explain away the actual design in the watch, nor is the reasoning that the watch was assembled by natural laws, since natural laws presuppose a lawmaker (Paley, 1802/2004, p. 36). Finally, even if all the previous arguments somehow fail, it would still be reasonable to assume a Designer of the watch since one knows the reason it exists – it has utility and a final purpose, such that one can infer that it has been designed; then it seems that, like the watch has a purpose, so too must the universe have purpose (Paley, 1802/2004, p. 36). Paley further philosophized what one could conclude if the watch had the ability to produce another watch, all by its existing mechanisms. He criticized the idea of infinite regress, arguing that design would still be left unexplained in an infinite regress of watches producing other watches (Paley, 1802/2004, p. 37-40). 

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz 

Leibniz, born 1646, was a major philosopher and mathematician. He argued that God must exist, which he derived from his principle of sufficient reason; the principle of sufficient reason states that everything must have a reason or cause. Thus, the question that arises is what caused the universe?

Leibniz (1714/2004) argued that there are two types of existence: contingent existence and necessary existence; things existing contingently means that they depend on something else to exist, and therefore need sufficient reason to exist; all physical things in the world, time, space, and the universe itself exists contingently. Thus, the universe cannot cause itself; the explanation must be found in something that exists necessarily; things that exist necessarily could not have been any other way; for example, it is necessarily true that two multiplied by two is four. Leibniz’s argument is that the universe exists contingently, and the sufficient reason or cause of the universe, must be God whose existence is not contingent but necessary (Leibniz, 1714/2004, p. 43). God is not contingent, meaning that a power like God does not depend on anything else, existing outside of contingent things like space and time (Leibniz, 1714/2004, p. 43). This renders the question “what caused God?” meaningless as the question presupposes contingency.

Also, see Leibniz's principle of perfection.


Critique & Discussion

Inspired by Darwin, Dawkins argues against design in favor of evolution and the mechanisms of natural selection. However, this could be challenged as one could suggest that evolution itself is designed. Furthermore, biological evolution does not address the argument of design in biological life emerging at all, or the fine-tuning of the existing natural laws in the universe. Dawkins and similar materialistic thinkers might be good technical scientists, but they are evidently poor philosophers as they do not give enough thought to the matter. Aquinas would argue that they do not have the right character.

David Hume argued that the effects we see in the world do not necessarily have a cause, especially if the effect has only occurred once, for example the universe coming into being. Paley had anticipated some of the criticism in his original work; Paley would have argued that this does not explain away the design that is there, regardless of it occurring only once. Notice that the multiverse theory does not explain away design.

Derek Parfit, an atheist philosopher, argued that there is no explanation needed for why the universe exists; it is a brute fact that it does, and further assumptions do not clarify the matter; however, Parfit himself admits that the brute fact view is not satisfactory. The universe could be eternal; thus, no sufficient reason would be necessary to explain its existence - it has always existed. To prove this assumption, one would have to prove Leibniz wrong, which in my opinion is near impossible. (Immanuel Kant ultimately argued for God's existence, but for very different reasons).

Leibniz assumes that the principle of sufficient reason is true; however, could this principle be false? If the principle of sufficient reason is false, the consequence is that anything can happen at any time, without any cause; this does not seem intuitively true, but the possibility of the principle being false might exist. However, the criticism itself does not make sense if Leibniz's principle is false. Aristotle argued that before any scientific investigation can be done, one must establish some basic principles one must assume to be true. Aristotle called these “first principles”; an example of a first principle is the principle of non-contradiction: something cannot possess an ability or attribute, and not possess it at the same time; any scientific investigation must presuppose this principle to be true. The method of discovering the “first principles” is through Aristotelian induction; Aristotle believed that the human mind could draw true general conclusions from few, but systematic observations. Therefore, the assumption that humans can use induction to gain certainty about the world is a fundamental starting point. If the principle of non-contradiction is not assumed, then any thought or statement becomes meaningless; the entire scientific endeavor becomes useless.



References

Leibniz, G. F. (2004). Monadology. In Crane, T., & Farkas K. (Eds.), Metaphysics: A Guide and Anthology (p. 43-44). Oxford University Press. (Original work published in 1714). 

Paley, W. (2004). Natural Theology. In Crane, T., & Farkas K. (Eds.), Metaphysics: A Guide and Anthology (p. 34-40). Oxford University Press. (Original work published in 1802).